The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) is a moral standard that was negotiated to protect everyone, whatever their views.
As shown in the previous two sections, there are several approaches to legitimise moral rules and they express their authority in different ways: the feeling of empathy, the commandments of a religion, the reasoning of philosophy or the evidence of science. These rules have emerged from different discourses, but they don’t necessarily conflict with each other in the behaviour that they recommend.
Human rights are another way of legitimising moral rules. They are a codification of behavioural standards which have been agreed by negotiation, for the protection of every individual in society – protections perceived as necessary to avoid conflict and oppression. The legitimacy of human rights is conferred by the negotiation process, not by an appeal to external authority or to philosophical reasoning, and they are expressed in a different kind of language. For example, the Biblical commandment not to murder is expressed in the language of rights by upholding the potential victim’s right to life.
The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR)was globally negotiated and enjoys considerable legitimacy. It is listed in its entirety in this book (Appendix 1). It underpins aspects of international law, as described later (5.3.6).
Compliance with human rights can provide an impartial measure of a government’s moral authority. Adam Smith argued for the value of impartiality in setting moral standards, in his book The Theory of Moral Sentiments:
“We endeavour to examine our own conduct as we imagine any other fair and impartial spectator would examine it.” [III, i, 2]
Amartya Sen quoted Smith in chapter 6 of his book, The Idea of Justice, when making the argument for countries to take account of views from outside their own borders. Sen saw compliance with international human rights as a test of a government’s moral legitimacy – and it is also an important part of political legitimacy (6.3.7).
Human rights are negotiable, they can be inclusive, and they can adapt to changes in culture – but they are inevitably a compromise between different viewpoints. People’s attitudes reflect whether they place a higher value on pursuit of the common good, or on individual liberty and responsibility. No one would suggest that an individual should have no rights, but there is room for discussion on what those rights should be:
· Their scope is contested, and international human rights have evolved with further negotiation following the original agreement of the UDHR (4.2.4.1). Countries bind themselves to compliance by signing treaties.
· Agreement is needed on enforcement (4.2.4.2), which is underpinned by the High Commissioner at the UN.
· The most contentious question is what level of socio-economic rights should be guaranteed to people, to protect them from hardship (4.2.4.3). Access to food, housing, education, and healthcare should be seen as economic, moral and political imperatives.
· The implementation of human rights is politically negotiated in each country, and they are sometimes embodied in the law (4.2.4.4).
· There are strong arguments for State-provision of many socio-economic rights (4.2.4.5), although it would always need to be supplemented by private charity.
· There are counter-arguments, for private provision of charity as an alternative means of delivering socio-economic rights (4.2.4.6), but private charity cannot be the only solution.
The answers to the first three questions depend partly upon the answer to the fourth question: how rights are negotiated. The definitions, quantification and delivery mechanisms of human rights will vary – depending on the outcome of the negotiations.
(This is an archive of a page intended to form part of Edition 4 of the Patterns of Power series of books. The latest versions are at book contents).